Modern History Sourcebook:
Immanuel Kant:
The Critique of Pure Reason, 1781
Excepts from The Critique of Pure Reason, 1781 [B edition]
I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical
Knowledge
That all our knowledge begins with experience there can be no
doubt. For how is it possible that the faculty of cognition should
be awakened into exercise otherwise than by means of objects which
affect our senses, and partly of themselves produce representations,
partly rouse our powers of understanding into activity, to compare
to connect, or to separate these, and so to convert the raw material
of our sensuous impressions into a knowledge of objects, which
is called experience? In respect of time, therefore, no knowledge
of ours is antecedent to experience, but begins with it.
But, though all our knowledge begins with experience, it by no
means follows that all arises out of experience. For, on the contrary,
it is quite possible that our empirical knowledge is a compound
of that which we receive through impressions, and that which the
faculty of cognition supplies from itself (sensuous impressions
giving merely the occasion), an addition which we cannot distinguish
from the original element given by sense, till long practice has
made us attentive to, and skilful in separating it. It is, therefore,
a question which requires close investigation, and not to be answered
at first sight, whether there exists a knowledge altogether independent
of experience, and even of all sensuous impressions? Knowledge
of this kind is called a priori, in contradistinction to empirical
knowledge, which has its sources a posteriori, that is, in experience.
But the expression, "a priori," is not as yet definite
enough adequately to indicate the whole meaning of the question
above started. For, in speaking of knowledge which has its sources
in experience, we are wont to say, that this or that may be known
a priori, because we do not derive this knowledge immediately
from experience, but from a general rule, which, however, we have
itself borrowed from experience. Thus, if a man undermined his
house, we say, "he might know a priori that it would have
fallen;" that is, he needed not to have waited for the experience
that it did actually fall. But still, a priori, he could not know
even this much. For, that bodies are heavy, and, consequently,
that they fall when their supports are taken away, must have been
known to him previously, by means of experience.
By the term "knowledge a priori," therefore, we shall
in the sequel understand, not such as is independent of this or
that kind of experience, but such as is absolutely so of all experience.
Opposed to this is empirical knowledge, or that which is possible
only a posteriori, that is, through experience. Knowledge a priori
is either pure or impure. Pure knowledge a priori is that with
which no empirical element is mixed up. For example, the proposition,
"Every change has a cause," is a proposition a priori,
but impure, because change is a conception which can only be derived
from experience.
II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is
in Possession of Certain Cognitions "a priori".
The question now is as to a criterion, by which we may securely
distinguish a pure from an empirical cognition. Experience no
doubt teaches us that this or that object is constituted in such
and such a manner, but not that it could not possibly exist otherwise.
Now, in the first place, if we have a proposition which contains
the idea of necessity in its very conception, it is a if, moreover,
it is not derived from any other proposition, unless from one
equally involving the idea of necessity, it is absolutely priori.
Secondly, an empirical judgement never exhibits strict and absolute,
but only assumed and comparative universality (by induction);
therefore, the most we can say is- so far as we have hitherto
observed, there is no except n to this or that rule. If, on the
other hand, a judgement carries with it strict and absolute universality,
that is, admits of no possible exception, it is not derived from
experience, but is valid absolutely a priori.
Empirical universality is, therefore, only an arbitrary extension
of validity, from that which may be predicated of a proposition
valid in most cases, to that which is asserted of a proposition
which holds good in all; as, for example, in the affirmation,
"All bodies are heavy." When, on the contrary, strict
universality characterizes a judgement, it necessarily indicates
another peculiar source of knowledge, namely, a faculty of cognition
a priori. Necessity and strict universality, therefore, are infallible
tests for distinguishing pure from empirical knowledge, and are
inseparably connected with each other. But in the use of these
criteria the empirical limitation is sometimes more easily detected
than the contingency of the judgement, or the unlimited universality
which we attach to a judgement is often a more convincing proof
than its necessity, it may be advisable to use the criteria separately,
each being by itself infallible.
Now, that in the sphere of human cognition we have judgements
which are necessary, and in the strictest sense universal, consequently
pure a priori, it will be an easy matter to show. If we desire
an example from the sciences, we need only take any proposition
in mathematics. If we cast our eyes upon the commonest operations
of the understanding, the proposition, "Every change must
have a cause," will amply serve our purpose. In the latter
case, indeed, the conception of a cause so plainly involves the
conception of a necessity of connection with an effect, and of
a strict universality of the law, that the very notion of a cause
would entirely disappear, were we to derive it, like David Hume,
from a frequent association of what happens with that which precedes;
and the habit thence originating of connecting representations-
the necessity inherent in the judgement being therefore merely
subjective. Besides, without seeking for such examples of principles
existing a priori in cognition, we might easily show that such
principles are the indispensable basis of the possibility of experience
itself, and consequently prove their existence a priori. For whence
could our experience itself acquire certainty, if all the rules
on which it depends were themselves empirical, and consequently
fortuitous? No one, therefore, can admit the validity of the use
of such rule as first principles. But, for the present, we may
content ourselves with having established the fact, that we do
possess and exercise a faculty of pure a priori cognition; and,
secondly, with having pointed out the proper tests of such cognition,
namely, universality and necessity.
Not only in judgements, however, but even in conceptions, is an
a priori origin manifest. For example, if we take away by degrees
from our conceptions of a body all that can be referred to mere
sensuous experience- colour, hardness or softness, weight, even
impenetrability- the body will then vanish; but the space which
it occupied still remains, and this it is utterly impossible to
annihilate in thought. Again, if we take away, in like manner,
from our empirical conception of any object, corporeal or incorporeal,
all properties which mere experience has taught us to connect
with it, still we cannot think away those through which we cogitate
it as substance, or adhering o substance, although our conception
of substance is more determined than that of an object. Compelled,
therefore, by that necessity with which the conception of substance
forces itself upon us, we must confess that it has its seat in
our faculty of cognition a priori.
III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which
shall Determine the Possibility, Principles, and Extent of Human
Knowledge "a priori."
Of far more importance than all that has been above said, is the
consideration that certain of our cognitions rise completely above
the sphere of all possible experience, and y means of conceptions,
to which there exists in the whole extent of experience no corresponding
object, seem to extend the range of our judgements beyond its
bounds. And just in this transcendental or supersensible sphere,
where experience affords us neither instruction nor guidance,
lie the investigations of reason, which, on account of their importance,
we consider far preferable to, and as having a far more elevated
aim than, all that the understanding can achieve within the sphere
of sensuous phenomena. So high a value do we set upon these investigations,
that even at the risk of error, we persist in following them out,
and permit neither doubt nor disregard nor indifference to restrain
us from the pursuit. These unavoidable problems of mere pure reason
are God, freedom (of will), and immortality. The science which,
with all its preliminaries, has for its especial object the solution
of these problems is named metaphysics- a science which is at
the very outset dogmatical, that is, it confidently takes upon
itself the execution of this task without any previous investigation
of the ability or inability of reason for such an undertaking.
Now the safe ground of experience being thus abandoned, it seems
nevertheless natural that we should hesitate to erect a building
with the cognitions we possess, without knowing whence they come,
and on the strength of principles, the origin of which is undiscovered.
Instead of thus trying to build without a foundation, it is rather
to be expected that we should long ago have put the question,
how e understanding can arrive at these a priori cognitions, and
what is the extent, validity, and worth which they may possess?
We say, "This is natural enough," meaning by the word
natural, that which is consistent with a just and reasonable way
of thinking; but if we understand by the term, that. which usually
happens, nothing indee could be more natural and more comprehensible
than that this investigation should be left long unattempted.
For one part of our pure knowledge, the science of mathematics,
has been long firmly established, and thus leads us to form flattering
expectations with regard to others, though these may be of quite
a different nature. Besides, when we get beyond the bounds of
experience, we are of course safe from opposition in that quarter;
and the charm of widening the range of our knowledge is so great
that, unless we are brought to a standstill by some evident contradiction,
we hurry on undoubtingly in our course. This, however, may be
avoided, if we are sufficiently cautious in the construction of
our fictions, which are not the less fictions on that account.
Mathematical science affords us a brilliant example, how far,
independently of all experience, we may carry our a priori knowledge.
It is true that the mathematician occupies himself with objects
and cognitions only in so far as they can be represented by means
of intuition. But this circumstance is easily overlooked, because
the said intuition can itself be given a priori, and therefore
is hardly to be distinguished from a mere pure conception. Deceived
by such a proof of the power of reason, we can perceive no limits
to the extension of our knowledge. The light dove cleaving in
free flight the thin air, whose resistance it feels, might imagine
that her movements would be far more free and rapid in airless
space. Just in the same way did Plato, abandoning the world of
sense because of the narrow limits it sets to the understanding,
venture upon the wings of ideas beyond it, into the void space
of pure intellect. He did not reflect that he made no real progress
by all his efforts; for he met with no resistance which might
serve him for a support, as it were, whereon to rest, and on which
he might apply his powers, in order to let the intellect acquire
momentum for its progress. It is, indeed, the common fate of human
reason in speculation, to finish the imposing edifice of thought
as rapidly as possible, and then for the first time to begin to
examine whether the foundation is a solid one or no. Arrived at
this point, all sorts of excuses are sought after, in order to
console us for its want of stability, or rather, indeed, to enable
Us to dispense altogether with so late and dangerous an investigation.
But what frees us during the process of building from all apprehension
or suspicion, and flatters us into the belief of its solidity,
is this. A great part, p haps the greatest part, of the business
of our reason consists in the analysation of the conceptions which
we already possess of objects. By this means we gain a multitude
of cognitions, which although really nothing more than elucidations
or explanations of that which (though in a confused manner) was
already thought in our conceptions, are, at least in respect of
their form, prized as new introspections; whilst, so far as regards
their matter or content, we have really made no addition to our
conceptions, but only disinvolved them. But as this process does
furnish a real priori knowledge, which has a sure progress and
useful results, reason, deceived by this, slips in, without being
itself aware of it, assertions of a quite different kind; in which,
to given conceptions it adds others, a priori indeed, but entirely
foreign to them, without our knowing how it arrives at these,
and, indeed, without such a question ever suggesting itself. I
shall therefore at once proceed to examine the difference between
these two modes of knowledge.
This text is part of the Internet Modern History Sourcebook.
The Sourcebook is a collection of public domain and copy-permitted
texts for introductory level classes in modern European and World
history.
Unless otherwise indicated the specific electronic form of the
document is copyright. Permission is granted for electronic copying,
distribution in print form for educational purposes and personal
use. If you do reduplicate the document, indicate the source.
No permission is granted for commercial use of the Sourcebook.
(c)Paul Halsall Aug 1997
halsall@murray.fordham.edu
|